Analytic
Aesthetics and the
Dilemma of Timelessness
My
topic today concerns analytic aesthetics not because I think
continental
versions don’t warrant attention but simply because I need to confine
my paper
to manageable limits, and because the problem – the dilemma – I want to
address
today is more clearly illustrated in the case of analytic aesthetics
than in its
continental counterpart. Some
basic points to begin: Analytic aesthetics, obviously, is an offshoot
of
analytic philosophy. It regularly discusses topics in literature and
music as
well as visual art and often turns its attention as well to general
issues such
as the nature of beauty, the Kantian notion of disinterestedness, the
nature of
“aesthetic pleasure” and so on. Managing the two main academic journals
in the
field – the British Journal of Aesthetics
and the American Journal of Aesthetics
and Art Criticism – analytic aesthetics is probably the most
active school
of philosophical aesthetics in the English-speaking world. Its impact
on neighbouring
disciplines such as art history and literary theory appears to be
limited, but to
the extent that philosophers in
Anglophone
contexts attempt to give an account of art in the general sense of the
word,
analytic aesthetics is probably the principal locus of activity. My
talk today examines certain assumptions underlying analytic aesthetics
(or the
analytic philosophy of art – the terms are more or less
interchangeable). The issues
I’ll consider are rarely discussed by analytic philosophers of art
themselves –
a matter of regret, as I’ll suggest – but they nevertheless tell us
much about
the field of study in question and the presuppositions on which it’s
based. The
focus of my paper is the relationship between art, in the general
sense, and
time – not time as presented within
works of art (how the passing of time might be represented in a novel
or a film,
for example) but time as an external
factor,
time understood as the changing historical contexts through which works
of art pass,
which in some cases stretch over centuries or even thousands of years.
In the
terminology I’ll employ here, the topic is the temporal nature of art
and a key
objective is to explore the assumptions of analytic aesthetics in this
regard.
What does this school of thought have to say about the temporal nature
of art?
What account does it give of the relationship between a work of art and
the effects
of historical change? Relatively specific though they seem, these
questions, I
believe, take us to the heart of analytic aesthetics and reveal some of
its major
characteristics. The
temporal nature of art, in the sense I’ve indicated here,
is by no means a new topic. It has an important history and although
that
history is rarely considered by philosophers of art of either the
analytic or the
continental stamp, it’s easy enough to trace. It begins with the
Renaissance. When
Renaissance artists rediscovered the works of antiquity – when they
eagerly dug
time-worn statues from the ruins of ancient Rome, or found new and
unsuspected beauties
in classical authors such as Horace and Plato –
they found themselves faced with a bewildering question. How was it
possible that
these ancient works, which had been neglected and despised for a
thousand
years, could still seem radiant with life? How had their peerless
beauty (for “beauty”
was the quality the Renaissance ascribed to them) survived across such
expanses
of time? The answer the Renaissance gave – an answer that would prove
hugely
influential in Western thought – was that unlike other objects, a work
of art has
a divine quality: art in all its forms, it was decided, is immune from
the passage
of time. It may, of course, be broken, destroyed or lost, but if it
survives,
its beauty is impervious to change.
Art
possesses the quite extraordinary feature that it exists outside
time. In terminology that would become standard for
centuries to come (but which would certainly have shocked medieval
minds for
whom divine qualities belonged to God alone) art is timeless, immortal,
eternal.
The
philosophical discipline called aesthetics was not
invented in its modern form until the eighteenth century but the
Renaissance had
no need of it to celebrate its discovery. I remember studying
Shakespeare’s
sonnets at school and encountering lines such as “Not marble, nor the gilded
monuments/Of princes, shall outlive this
powerful rhyme…”, and I remember being told that the idea that a
beautiful poem
is immortal was simply a flight of Elizabethan poetic fancy, a “poet’s
conceit”
it was called. It was clever, certainly, but not to be taken too
seriously. That,
however, was a misunderstanding because there was much more at stake.
The idea
expressed in lines such as these was central to Renaissance thinking
and explains
why art in all its forms (and the very word “art”) was held in
unprecedented esteem
from then on, and why the idea is found again
and again in other writers
of the times such as Petrarch, Ronsard, Drayton and Spenser – and also Michelangelo who, as well as
being a painter and
sculptor, wrote poetry, and who writes in a sonnet entitled The Artist and His Work that “[art’s]
wonders live in spite of
time and death, those tyrants stern”.[1]
The immortality of art was
an idea that the
intellectual world of the time embraced with enthusiasm. It was part of
the ideology of the Renaissance, if one can
put it that way – as
much a part of the Renaissance world-view as, say, belief in the powers
of
science is for us today. The idea was, moreover, destined for a long and
illustrious life. So influential was it, indeed, that Romantic poets
were still
celebrating it centuries later, as the French poet and art critic
Théophile
Gautier did, for instance, in his poem Art which proclaims
that “All
things pass. Sturdy art/Alone is eternal”.[2] More importantly for present
purposes, the same
conviction was central to the beliefs of the eighteenth-century
thinkers who
laid the foundations of the philosophical discipline we know as
aesthetics. The
evidence is plain to see. David Hume writes in his well-known and
highly
influential essay Of
the Standard of Taste
that the
function of a suitably prepared sense of taste is to discern that
“catholic
and universal beauty” found in all true works of art, and that the
forms of
beauty thus detected will “while the world endures … maintain their
authority
over the mind of man”, a proposition Hume supports by his familiar
dictum that
“The same Homer who pleased at Athens and Rome two thousand years ago,
is still
admired at Paris and London”.[3]
This belief was undisputed – indeed, by this time, it was simply taken
for
granted – and it received endorsement from a chorus of other
Enlightenment voices
including the influential art historian of the times, Johann
Winckelmann, the
poet Alexander Pope, the painter Sir Joshua Reynolds in his Discourses on Art and Immanuel Kant in
his Critique of Judgement. In
short,
where the relationship between art and the passing of time is
concerned, the
Enlightenment gave a firm stamp of approval to the well-established
view. The
Renaissance had declared art immune from time – timeless, eternal,
immortal – and
the Enlightenment was in full accord. Now,
aesthetics as we know it today,
especially aesthetics of the analytic variety is, as I’m sure you know,
in a direct
line of descent from eighteenth
century thinkers
such as Hume and Kant and if one had any doubts about that, one would
only need
peruse the two journals I mentioned earlier where articles on aspects
of Hume, Kant
and their contemporaries are part of the staple fare. Two obvious
questions arise
therefore: Does modern analytic aesthetics endorse
the view of its Enlightenment forefathers that art endures timelessly?
And if
not, does it offer an alternative explanation? Before
looking more closely at those questions, I’d like to pause a moment to
reflect
on the significance of the issues at stake. Let us consider the history
of
literature, for example. We know that of the thousands of novels
published in
the eighteenth century (for instance), only a tiny fraction holds our
interest
today, and that for every Tom Jones
or Les Liaisons dangereuses, there
are large numbers of works by contemporaries of Fielding and Laclos
that have
sunk into oblivion, probably permanently. And if we go a step further
and think
about objects outside the world of art, the point is equally true. We
do not
ask, for example, if a map of the world drawn by a cartographer of the
Elizabethan
era is still a reliable navigational tool, and we know that a ship’s
captain
today who relied on such a map would be very unwise. But we might quite
sensibly ask if Shakespeare’s plays, written at the time the map was
drawn, is
still pertinent to life today, and we might well want to answer yes.
The map
survives as an object of “historical interest” but it’s no longer
applicable to
the world we live in. Shakespeare’s plays, however, are not just part
of
history (although one might also view
them in that light); they have endured in a way the map has not.
So
there is something very real and important at stake here, which applies
not
only to literature, of course, but to art in all its forms. One of
art’s
specific characteristics, we are entitled to say, is a power to endure
– to defy,
or transcend, time – and this is something our experience confirms
every time
we respond to a great work of art from the past. The nature
of this power is a separate question: as we’ve seen, the
Renaissance and the Enlightenment believed that art endures because it
is
exempt from time – timeless – and we shall see shortly that this is not
the
only possibility. But setting that question aside for the moment, one
can at
least say that the power to transcend time is a specific
characteristic of art, a characteristic as real and
evident as any that aesthetics, rightly or wrongly, traditionally
ascribes to
art – such as a capacity to give “aesthetic pleasure”, to “represent
the world”,
to respond to a sense of taste, and so on. If, in other words, one
wishes to
give a full account of the nature of literature, or of art generally,
the capacity
of certain works – those of Chaucer, Shakespeare, Michelangelo, Titian,
Mozart,
Monteverdi and many others – to transcend time is one that cannot be
ignored. There
is another, related point. As I’ve mentioned, timelessness is not the
only conceivable
way art might endure. In principle at least, art’s power of endurance
might
operate in a number of ways. Works of art might,
for example, endure for
a predetermined lengthy period then disappear definitively into
oblivion. They
might endure for a time, disappear, and then return – in a cyclical
way. They might
endure timelessly – the alternative under consideration at the moment.
And, as
we shall see later, there is at least one other possibility. So, by
itself,
a recognition that art has a special power to endure, important though
that is,
leaves us with an unanswered question, an explanatory gap. How,
one needs
to know, does art endure? Or to put the matter slightly differently:
What does
enduring mean in the case of art? Now, I shall
argue shortly that for us
today, the traditional claim that art is timeless has become
unacceptable, but we
should at least acknowledge that it gave an answer to the question of
what
enduring means. Art endures, it said, not simply because it persists in
time in
some unknown, unspecified way, but because it is impervious to
time,
“time-less”, unaffected by the passing parade of history, its meaning
and value
always remaining the same. So whatever one may think about the notion
of
timelessness, it was at least a complete solution. It did not merely
assert that
art endures; it described the nature of
the enduring and the explanatory gap was closed. This, perhaps, is one
of the
reasons why the idea held sway for so long in European culture: here
was an
account of art’s seemingly miraculous power to transcend time that left
no conceptual
questions unanswered. But
let us return now to the question I left in abeyance a moment ago.
Where does analytic aesthetics
stand on the issue under
discussion? Does it endorse the view of its Enlightenment forefathers
that art
endures because it is timeless? And if not, what alternative
explanation does it
offer? What, in other words, has been the contribution of analytic
aesthetics to this topic which,
as we now see, has a long and important history in Western culture? Without
doubt, the most striking feature of analytic
aesthetics’ contribution is how slight
it has been. Indeed, the topic
has been all but forgotten. Textbooks seldom discuss it or even carry
an index
reference; the two leading journals, mentioned earlier, rarely carry an
article
with anything more than tangential relevance; and the topic is
conspicuously
absent from courses of study. Many other issues inherited from
Enlightenment writers
are discussed regularly – such as the nature of “aesthetic pleasure”,
whether
disinterestedness is essential to one’s response to art, the meaning of
beauty,
what exactly Hume meant by taste and so on; indeed, these are staples
of modern
analytic aesthetics. But the Enlightenment’s assertion that art is
timeless is
almost entirely ignored, and no alternative is suggested. Thus, a
stream of
thought that had its source in the Renaissance, deeply influenced
Enlightenment
thinking about art and beauty, and carried on through the Romantic
period, has effectively
run dry. Analytic aesthetics displays little or no interest in the
relationship
between art and the passing of time. Ignoring
an issue, however, does not necessarily make it go away. And, indeed,
there are
clear indications that although analytic aesthetics rarely gives
explicit
endorsement to the Enlightenment view that art is timeless, its practice as a school of thought typically
implies that it accepts this view – or at least that it assumes that
art is atemporal in some unknown
and unexplained
way. Hence the characteristically static feel of analytic aesthetics –
its reluctance
to offer explanations of art that consider historical factors in any
but
peripheral ways, its tendency to focus on topics such as “aesthetic
pleasure”,
disinterestedness, definitions of beauty and so on, that can plausibly
be discussed
without reference to temporal considerations. Hence also a fondness for
the
idea of artistic “universals” – features of art said to transcend time
and
place.[4]
Hence
as well, the tendency
of analytic aesthetics to hold itself at arms’ length from the
discipline of
art history as if to imply that art is best understood in abstract,
timeless or
atemporal terms, free from the distractions of historical
“contingencies”.[5]
Explicit
appeals to the notion of timelessness are infrequent (though not
unknown, as we
shall see in a moment) but in its philosophical practice,
analytic aesthetics’ affinities with Enlightenment
thinking and the assumption that art is timeless are not difficult to
discern. Now
and then, the notion of timelessness is, however, given something
resembling explicit
approval. Comparing analytic aesthetics to other approaches, one
prominent contemporary
representative of the analytic school writes that the continental
school “is more
historically oriented” while the analytic approach “tends to examine
issues
about the nature of art and the aesthetic qualities of objects in an
ahistorical
manner”.[6]
And
in a similar vein, though with a puzzling “more” qualifying the term
“timeless”,
the same writer argues in a recent issue of the Journal
of Aesthetics and Art Criticism that the value we place on
a work of art is due not just to its historical significance but to its
capacity “to engage the mind, the imagination, and the senses with some
more
timeless interest”, these qualities allowing a work to “enter a more
timeless
canon of literature”.[7]
(I say the word “more” is puzzling here because in the proper sense of
the
word, “timeless” – like “unique” for example – cannot be qualified. Its
meaning
is outside of, or exempt from, time.) Other philosophers of
art occasionally express
similar sentiments. One essay in the British Journal of Aesthetics declares,
for
instance, that “There is a tendency among scholars and non-scholars
alike to
think that art works, or more specifically, great art works, are in
some sense
immortal”, the writer adding that he himself sees “some truth in the
view”.[8]
Another
article in the same journal asserts that “Classics are timeless and
transcendental, appealing to all historical eras, because they capture
what is
essential about humanity”, the
suggestion apparently being that great art is timeless because it
expresses
timeless truths.[9]
Significant
though they are, comments such as these are, nevertheless, the
exception rather
than the rule: in general, as I’ve indicated, analytic aesthetics
simply ignores
the question of the temporal nature of art and passes over it in
silence. Taken
together with the predispositions in philosophical practice
I mentioned above, however, comments of this kind
clearly suggest
that the proposition that art endures timelessly remains very
influential, even
if that fact is rarely acknowledged. The
question then arises: Can this proposition still be sustained today? Is
it
still plausible to go on believing – or assuming – that art endures
timelessly?
When we think about it, it’s not difficult to imagine why it seemed
very
plausible to Renaissance and Enlightenment minds. Their world of art
was much narrower
than ours, its boundaries extending no further than European art from
the
Renaissance onwards and selected works from antiquity. In these
circumstances,
it was doubtless easy enough to conclude – as in fact it was
concluded – that the reason why the “timeless” works of
antiquity were despised for so long was simply that there had been an
interregnum
of cultural barbarism during which the achievements of ancient Greece
and Rome had
been misunderstood. For us today, however, circumstances are very
different. Our
world of art is much larger and much more varied, encompassing works
from the
four corners of the earth and from periods of time stretching back to
the
Palaeolithic; and we are much less inclined to dismiss the achievements
of earlier
cultures as barbaric, especially since it is from just these cultures
that many
of the objects we now regard as major works of art have come. How
reasonable is
it, then, to endorse the concept of timelessness today?
The
problem can be brought into sharp focus if one thinks of examples in
visual art
where objects have often lasted longer, time scales are lengthier and
the
effects of the passage of time more obvious. Consider an ancient
Egyptian sculpture
such as the four-and a half-thousand-year-old statue of the Pharaoh
Djoser now
in the Cairo museum, a work, which despite its battered state, is now
generally
regarded as one of the treasures of world art. What did this statue
mean to the
ancient Egyptians? Doubtless we shall never know exactly given the
difficulties
of fully understanding the world-views of ancient civilizations even
when, as
with Egypt, there is substantial written evidence. We can, however,
feel quite
safe in asserting that the image was not regarded as a “work of art” in
any of
the senses that idea has had for Western culture – first, because we
know that,
like many cultures, ancient Egypt had no word or concept “art”, and
second,
because we know that the statue in question had a purely religious
purpose and
was placed in the pharaoh’s mortuary temple to receive offerings to aid
him in
the afterlife. Immediately,
therefore, the theory of timelessness receives a major blow. Clearly,
this sculpted
image did not originally have
the meaning and
importance it has for us today: we are not speaking of the “the same
Djoser”,
to adapt Hume’s dictum about Homer that I quoted earlier. But that’s
not the
only difficulty. We today regard the image of Djoser as important
because we consider
it to be a major work of art. But not so long ago – as recently as the
mid-nineteenth century in fact – that judgement would have been
universally rejected.
Nineteenth century art lovers (for whom “art” meant classical
sculptures such
as the Apollo Belvedere and works
of
painters such as Raphael and Titian) excluded Egyptian sculpture from
the
rubric art as rigorously as they excluded objects from tribal Africa,
medieval times,
Hindu India, the Pacific Islands and much more. Objects from cultures
such as
these sometimes found their way into cabinets
de curiosités and, later, into archaeological collections,
but at no point
in European history had they ever
been art: they belonged to the obscure realm of idols and fetishes that
had nothing
to do with art. So, returning to the Egyptian example, not only does
the Pharaoh Djoser have a
significance for
us today quite different from the significance it held in ancient
Egypt, but
there were also long periods of time when, for Western culture, it had
no
significance at all – when, like
countless objects from other cultures we now regard as art, it dwelt in
a
cultural limbo. Where,
then, does this leave the notion of timelessness – the idea born with
the
Renaissance, vital to Enlightenment aesthetics, and, as we’ve seen,
still
influential in analytic aesthetics today, that works of art are
impervious to time
and change, their meaning and importance unaffected by history?
Clearly, the
idea is left in a parlous state since in cases such as the one just
considered
– and they are legion – time and change have manifestly had a major
effect. And
changing the focus to literature, let’s look again at Hume’s famous
claim. Is it
true that the same Homer – the same
Homer – who pleased at Athens and Rome two thousand years ago was the
Homer admired
in eighteenth century Paris and London – or the Homer we admire today?
The
early history of the Iliad – to
take
that as our example – is rather
obscure but we do know certain
things. We know
that it was originally sung not recited, and certainly not read
silently from the
pages of a book. We also know that the gods and heroes of the story
were figures
in whom the Greeks of the time firmly believed, not personages from
“Greek mythology”
as the eighteenth century saw them, and as we regard them today.
Moreover,
there is little doubt that the modern practice of regarding the Iliad as “literature”, to be placed on
the same footing as epics of other ancient peoples, such as Gilgamesh or the Bhagavad Gita, would have been unthinkable to Greek
communities circa 750 BC
when the Iliad was composed – as
unthinkable as
placing the image of the Pharaoh Djoser in an art museum on the same
footing as
gods from other cultures would have been in the eyes of ancient
Egyptians. How then
do we identify a “timeless” Iliad
persisting
across the millennia unchanged? Where is the immunity from historical
change
required by the notion of timelessness? Examples
such as Egyptian sculpture and the Iliad
provide vivid illustrations of the dilemma facing the notion of
timelessness
because the time scales are lengthy and the changes dramatic and easy
to see.
But the same issues arise, even if less obviously, when we consider
more recent
works. Is “our” Shakespeare – Shakespeare as we respond to him today –
the same
as the Shakespeare of audiences circa 1600? He certainly seems to
differ from
the Shakespeare of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries when
audiences preferred
his plays substantially rewritten, often with different endings –
something we
would undoubtedly balk at today. Closer to our times, how do we square
the
notion of timelessness with Laclos’s Les
Liaisons dangereuses which was attacked for its immorality
when first
published, sank from sight during the nineteenth century with the
advent of
Romanticism, and is now prized for its psychological finesse and rated
as one
of the finest of French novels? And has Dickens’ picture of nineteenth
century urban
life, bleak though it often is, ever seemed quite as bleak since
Dostoevsky
described Raskolnikov’s descent into Hell
in the streets
of St. Petersburg? Examples like this are endless, particularly if one
broadens
the scope to include visual art and music. Countless mediaeval works,
such as
the statues and stained glass at Notre-Dame de Chartres, fell into a
limbo of indifference
for centuries before remerging in the twentieth century as “works of
art” – something
they had never been. Vermeer faded from view for over two hundred years
as did
Georges de la Tour. Music has the same tale to tell. The religious
compositions
of Tallis and Byrd disappeared into near oblivion for centuries and are
admired
today as art and not solely for religious reasons as they were
originally. For nineteenth-century
music lovers enamoured of Beethoven and Brahms, Mozart survived
principally as the
standard-bearer for classical restraint – “perfect grace” to employ a
stock
phrase still used by some writers in aesthetics. But is this our Mozart today? “Perfect grace”
hardly seems to do justice to the poignancy of the slow movements of
the piano
concertos, the drama and pathos of Don
Giovanni, the driving energy of the Prague
Symphony, or the haunting grandeur of the Requiem.
And as perceptions of Mozart have changed in recent times,
so have responses to the music of the Romantics: as Mozart alters, so
do
Beethoven and Brahms. Music, in short, is as ill-suited to the
Procrustean bed of
timelessness – of immunity from historical change – as literature and
visual
art. Two
clear implications flow from all this: first, it seems quite
unacceptable to ignore
the relationship between art and time as analytic aesthetics has done
since its
inception, given that the effects of time are both obvious and
profound; and
second, the traditional explanation of this relationship – that art is
timeless
– is no longer viable. Ingrained in conventional thinking though it
often is,
that explanation has ceased to be believable and something new must be
found. Analytic
aesthetics, regrettably, gives us no help here. Not only, as we have
seen, does
it pay scant attention to the temporal nature of art, but to the
limited extent
it deals with the issue, it simply reiterates the Enlightenment belief,
which
the Enlightenment inherited from the Renaissance, that art endures
timelessly. If
we remain within the conceptual limits of analytic aesthetics,
therefore, we
are left with a dilemma – a major, insoluble dilemma.[10]
My
own belief is that the dilemma is far from insoluble and that a very
persuasive
solution has been offered by the much-neglected twentieth century art
theorist,
André Malraux. I’m not going to attempt to explain Malraux’s account in
detail[11]
partly
because the purpose of my talk is not to proselytize for Malraux’s
theory of
art – worthy cause though that would be – but also because my main
purpose is
to explore the general question of the temporal nature of art and
evaluate the
contribution of analytic aesthetics. It may be useful, nevertheless, to
indicate briefly the nature of Malraux solution if only to show that
there is at
least one serious alternative to the traditional notion of
timelessness. One
way of approaching Malraux’s position is as follows: If an object is
timeless,
it has an essence that is impervious to change – key elements that
retain the
same meaning and importance across the centuries, even if peripheral
aspects are
sometimes affected.[12]
Empires can rise and fall, customs and beliefs can change radically,
but the
significance of the work – be it literature, visual art, or music –
will always
stay the same. The “same Homer” who pleased at Athens and Rome will be
admired
in eighteenth century Paris and London, and, presumably, endlessly
thereafter.
If there are any lapses in admiration, that would be due simply to an
unfortunate
interregnum of barbarism. But
it is possible to think of the essence of a work of art in a quite
different
way. Suppose one thinks of it as the characteristic that enables a work
to
endure not by retaining the same meaning and importance across the ages
but by
assuming different meanings and different kinds of importance – “living
on”, as we say, not
by being impervious to change but by responding
to change, by being reborn with new and different
significances. One
can see immediately how effectively this explanation would deal with
problems of
the kind I have raised. Consider Pharaoh
Djoser again. We saw how badly the timelessness explanation –
perhaps one
might call it the Humean explanation – fared in the face of the fact
that the original
meaning and importance of the image were so different from the meaning
and
importance it has assumed today, and the additional fact that there
were long
periods of time when it had no meaning or importance at all.
Transformations of
this kind – and this example is only one of hundreds – are impossible
to square
with the proposition that art is impervious to time. But if art endures
through change, by means of change, these problems
instantly disappear. For then one
can simply say this: In ancient Egypt, the statue was a powerful
manifestation of
a religious truth. When Egyptian civilization died, so did that
significance of
the image, and since it had no other, it simply lay gathering dust for
four
thousand years. But unlike the customs and beliefs of ancient Egypt,
which have
disappeared forever, the imposing Pharaoh
Djoser has returned to life today and taken on a new meaning
and importance
– as what we call a work of art. Like so many other works of genius
from
earlier cultures – from Buddhist India to Mesopotamia to Romanesque
Europe – it
has shed its original significance and, after a period in limbo,
re-emerged in
modern Western civilization as a work of art, surviving not because it
retains
its original significance, as Hume and his Enlightenment contemporaries
would
have it, but because it has a power of metamorphosis (to employ
Malraux’s term)
– a power of resurrection and transformation that enables it to live
again,
albeit with a meaning and importance of a different kind. The argument obviously
presents a radical
challenge to traditional thinking, but it is neither obscure nor
far-fetched.
As Malraux commented in a television program about visual art in 1975, For us
today, metamorphosis isn’t something arcane; it stares us in the face.
To talk
about “immortal art” today, faced with the history of art as we know
it, is
simply empty words. Every work has a power of resurrection or it
doesn’t. If it
doesn’t, end of story; but if it survives it’s by a process of
resurrection not
by immortality.[13] There
is much more to say about Malraux’s concept of metamorphosis[14]
but
I’m hoping that this brief account will be enough to show that there is
certainly
a credible alternative to the notion of timelessness and that the
dilemma
confronting analytic aesthetics is by no means insoluble. But why, we
surely
need to ask, does analytic aesthetics find itself in this quandary? Why
does it
find itself shackled to the unworkable assumption that art is timeless,
or at
least atemporal in some unexplained way? Evidence
of the kind I’ve discussed today suggests, I believe, that the answer
lies in analytic
aesthetics’ continuing dependence on its eighteenth century origins.
Enlightenment aesthetics, as I’ve said, accepted the Renaissance claim
that art
endures timelessly and when it emerged as a philosophical discipline in
the
eighteenth century, it framed its agenda on that basis, both in terms
of the questions
posed and the kinds of answers given. Consciously or not, analytic
aesthetics
has simply followed suit, choosing
many
of the same issues for discussion and dealing with them in similar ways.[15]
On
the specific question of the temporal nature of art, analytic
aesthetics has usually
been more reticent that its Enlightenment forebears, perhaps because it
is
uncomfortably aware that the world of art as we know it today poses
problems
that Hume, Kant and their contemporaries were never required to face;
but the
general orientation – the static approach discussed earlier, in which
art inhabits
a realm of inert abstractions – nonetheless remains firmly in place.
Analytic aesthetics,
in other words, lives essentially in a world without history, a world
in which
the passage of time is of peripheral importance and where, by
consequence, the
crucial capacity of art to transcend time – one of its key features as
I’ve argued
– is rarely mentioned. Discussion is rigorously confined to issues such
as the
nature of aesthetic pleasure, or the meaning of beauty, or whether the
appreciation of art should be disinterested, or others of that ilk,
which can
be partitioned off from historical change and encased in a tightly
sealed world
where time stands permanently still and where, just as importantly the
question
of art’s capacity to transcend time is never raised. In
a very real sense, in other words, analytic aesthetics is, in my view,
a
prisoner of a its intellectual inheritance. The writings on aesthetics
of Kant,
Hume and their contemporaries have in many respects assumed the status
of quasi-sacred
texts – works that one may approach as a humble exegete, and even at
times respectfully
disagree with, but certainly not challenge in any fundamental way or
set aside.
This is clearly unsatisfactory. Kant, Hume and their contemporaries did
not
live in a cultural vacuum, and whatever might be said about their
philosophies
in general, their thinking about art, including the relationship
between art
and time, was not immune from the influences of the era in which they
lived –
far from it, as I have suggested.[16]
The Enlightenment took it for granted that art endures timelessly
because no
one had thought otherwise for at least two hundred years, and because,
as I’ve
said, that view doubtless seemed believable at a period in European
history when
the world of art was far narrower than ours. But today the proposition
simply makes
no sense. As Malraux aptly comments, “To talk about ‘immortal art’
today, faced
with the history of art as we know it, is simply empty words.” If
analytic
aesthetics is to escape the realm of empty words, I believe, it needs
to give
careful thought to the Enlightenment inheritance that seems to hold it
in thrall.
November
2014 References Allan, Derek. Art and the Human Adventure: André Malraux's
Theory of Art. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2009. Allan, Derek. Art and
Time.
Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2013. Crowther, Paul. The
Transhistorical
Image. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002. Symonds, J.A., ed. The
Sonnets of Michelangelo.J.A. Symonds. London: Vision Press,
1950. [1] J.A. Symonds, ed. The
Sonnets of Michelangelo (London: Vision Press, 1950). Sonnet XVII. [2] Théophile Gautier: L’Art.
Émaux et Camées. My
translation. [3] David Hume, Of
the Standard of Taste, and other essays, ed. J.W. Lenz
(Indianapolis:
Bobbs-Merrill, 1965), 9. [4] Sometimes termed “transhistorical” features.
See, for example: Paul Crowther, The
Transhistorical Image (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2002). [5] As one commentator observes, the disciplines
of aesthetics and art
history “pass each other like ships in the night”. Keith Moxey,
"Aesthetics is Dead: Long Live
Aesthetics," in Art History versus
Aesthetics, ed. James Elkins (New York: Routledge, 2006),
166-172, 167. [6] Peter Lamarque, Analytic
Approaches to Aesthetics: Oxford Bibliographies Online Research Guide
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), Introduction. [7] Peter Lamarque,
"The Uselessness of Art", The Journal of
Aesthetics and Art Criticism 68,
no. 3 (2010),
205-214. 213. [8] Christopher
Perricone, "Art and the Metamorphosis
of Art into History", British
Journal of Aesthetics, 31, no. 4
(1991), 310-321. 310. [9] A. Hamilton,
"Scruton’s Philosophy of Culture:
Elitism, Populism, and Classic Art", British
Journal of Aesthetics, 4, no. 49
(2009), 389-404. 403. Analytic aesthetics has a fondness for the
idea of timeless truths.
Like the related notion of human nature, however, the idea has clearly
taken a
severe battering over the past century or so. See my discussion in Derek Allan, Art
and Time (Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing,
2013), 141,
142. [10] Jerrold Levinson, a representative of the
analytic school, attempts
to escape the ahistorical confines of analytic aesthetics by providing
what he
terms an “historical definition of art”. For Levinson, art can be
“defined
historically” via a sequence of “regards-as-art” stretching back into
the past,
his proposition being that “something is art if and only if it is or
was
intended or projected for overall regard as some prior art is or was
correctly
regarded”. The argument quickly collapses in the face of historical
evidence,
given that the concept “art” in anything resembling its modern sense
was
unknown as late as medieval times and absent from a wide range of
non-Western
cultures and early civilizations. The chain of supposed “art regards”
would therefore
peter out long before one reached many of the cultures from which large
numbers
of objects that we today term “art” have come. In other words, this
“historical”
concept of art is essentially unresponsive to history. Jerrold Levinson,
"The Irreducible Historicality
of the Concept of Art", British
Journal of Aesthetics, 42, no. 4
(2002), 367-379; Jerrold Levinson, "Defining Art
Historically," in Aesthetics and the
Philosophy of Art: The Analytic Tradition ed. Peter Lamarque
and Stein
Haugom Olsen (Oxford: Blackwell, 2005), 35-46. [11] I have done so in Allan, Art and
Time. Also
in Derek Allan, Art
and the Human Adventure: André Malraux's Theory of Art
(Amsterdam: Rodopi,
2009), esp. Chapter Six. [12] For example, the language of Shakespeare’s
plays often seems
antiquated today; but the theory of timelessness can accommodate this
simply by
saying that the essence of each of the plays – their core meaning – is
unaffected. [13] André Malraux, Promenades
imaginaires dans Florence. (Television series: Journal de Voyage avec
André
Malraux.) (Paris: Interviewer: Jean-Marie Drot 1975). [14] It is important to see that Malraux is
speaking about metamorphosis
as an endless process (so that even the condition “work of art” is not
a
terminus). Peter Lamarque, one of the few analytic writers who
occasionally addresses
questions related to the temporal nature of art, argues that a work
starts out
with “pragmatic” value and gradually takes on “artistic” value, or
value “for
its own sake”. The terms themselves pose obvious difficulties but, in
any case,
one is still restricted to the notion of timelessness since the
“artistic
value” phase is apparently permanent. Peter Lamarque,
"Historical Embeddedness and
Artistic Autonomy," in Aesthetic and
Artistic Autonomy, ed. Owen Hulatt (London: Bloomsbury,
2103), 51-63. [15] Hegel, Marx and their successors, who
introduced an historical
dimension, and who have been influential in continental aesthetics,
have been
of marginal importance in the analytic context. [16] Arguably, other
aspects of their thinking were also heavily influenced by the cultural
context.
The notion of taste and the proposition that art exists simply to
afford a
certain kind of pleasure were very much “in the air” in the eighteenth
century.
These issues are beyond the scope of the present essay. |
A paper presented to a seminar in the School of Philosophy at the Australian National University, 11 November 2014.Comment 10 on this page is also relevant. |