Creation Ex Nihilo: André
Malraux and the Concept of
Artistic Creation
I’d
like to investigate this topic via the
French art theorist, André
Malraux – a name that may not mean a lot to you because his work has
been
neglected in recent times. But Malraux developed a very powerful theory
of art
which, among many other things, includes an explanation of what
creation means
in the case of art, an explanation that I shall try to describe as
succinctly
as possible. Malraux
was born in 1901 and died in 1976. He fought in
the Spanish Civil War and later against the Nazis in the Second World
War, both
in the army and in the Resistance, so, he was well acquainted with the
various horrors
the times. Together with a series of intellectual developments, the
events of
the 20th century, Malraux believed, had left
Western civilization
without any firmly-held belief in the significance of human existence.
God, he
agreed, was certainly dead, but that was not all. The Enlightenment had
replaced God with a faith in rational, civilized man, and that faith
was now
dead as well. The nineteenth century had developed a revised form of
humanism
based on science, progress and the ideal of new and better humanity yet
to be born.
But the 20th century had killed that too and now
nothing was left. So
as early as 1926, Malraux had written: “Absolute reality for us was
God; then
man. But man
is
dead, after God, and we are now engaged in an anguished
search for
something to which we can assign his strange inheritance…” (And this,
incidentally,
was some four decades before Foucault was edging towards the same idea
in his
book The Order of Things.) These
convictions
remained with Malraux throughout his life; so in 1957, for example, in The Metamorphosis of the Gods, he
describes the modern Western world as the first civilization that “is
aware that
it does not understand man’s significance”. Or as he put it elsewhere:
“Here is
the first civilization capable of conquering the world, but not of
inventing
its own temples or its own tombs.”[1] But our
subject is art, so how does all this relate to art? Well,
first of all, if man is dead, the aesthetic theories
– the philosophies of art – that depend on the ideals of man in
question are
necessarily dead too; and this is no small matter. The aesthetic
theories that
depend on Enlightenment notions of man are those of major figures such
as Hume
and Kant – theories that explain art in terms of familiar notions such
as
“judgement of taste”, “aesthetic sense”, “aesthetic pleasure” and so
on. And
the philosophies of art born of 19th century
concepts of man are
those that argue that art is tied in some systematic way to processes
of
historical change – which means the theories of such prominent figures
such as
Hegel, Marx, and Taine. If man is dead, those too are consigned to the
archives
of intellectual history. And along with all that, of course, go the
many
contemporary aesthetic theories – both analytic and continental – that
still
depend on these 18th and 19th
century foundations. Thus,
the consequences of the death of man in the field of art theory are
severe, to
say the least. The aesthetic theories of thinkers such as Hume, Kant,
Hegel,
and Marx, together with their modern descendants, are still of
historical
interest, but of historical interest only. So, if Malraux has a theory of art – and he certainly does – where does he begin. If, as he says, we today know that we do not understand man’s significance, what foundation does he build on when he describes the nature and purpose of art? In short, if man is dead, where to now? Malraux
discovered a new way forward during a particularly
dramatic experience in 1934 which laid the foundations for his thinking
about
art and for many other things as well. Unfortunately, time doesn’t
permit me to
describe the experience, but I can describe the thinking that resulted.
Malraux
found no answer to the question: What is man? On
that score he remained an agnostic – like most of us today, he
believes. But he
discovered something more fundamental: he discovered the primordial
human
capacity to pose the question at
stake. He discovered what he terms “the fundamental emotion man feels
in the
face of life, beginning with his own”[2]
and that emotion, he argues, is inseparable from the questions: “Why is
there
something rather than nothing?” and “Why has life taken this form?”[3]
This fundamental feeling of estrangement and perplexity, Malraux
argues, is at
the root of human consciousness itself. It is, simultaneously, an
awareness of
the world as a chaos of fleeting appearances and
of the possibility of resisting that chaos; it is an awareness
that everything, including man and all his endeavours, seems to be
without the
least significance, but at the same time an awareness of the
possibility of
conferring significance on man and his endeavours. In short, Malraux
discovered
the fundamental human capacity to call the world into question: a
capacity, if
not to understand man’s significance, at least to ask that question
and, in so
doing, to be more than a blind victim of meaninglessness and chaos. This
discovery gave Malraux the answer to two crucial
questions. It explained the nature of an absolute, and it also
explained the
fundamental nature of art. An
absolute, he argues – such as a religion or even a
powerful secular ideology – reveals an underlying unity beneath the
chaos of fleeting
appearances; it provides a definitive
answer to the questions: “Why is there something rather than
nothing?” and
“Why has life taken this form?”[4]
A Christian, for example, might answer that the world is the way it is
because
it is the will of the Creator God; a secular ideology might answer that
the
underlying meaning is to be found in History – with a capital H – which
is
moving towards an ultimate goal, such as a classless society. And, of
course,
there have been many other responses. Then what is art? Art, Malraux
replies, also replaces
chaos with unity but, unlike an absolute, it gives no definitive
answers.
Art responds to the same
fundamental emotion I have described, but it does so by creating
another world, a rival world,
not
necessarily a supernal world, or a glorified one, but nevertheless a
unified
world – constructed solely of elements that, are the way they are, and
are
present,
for a reason. Art, Malraux writes, creates a world “scaled down to
man’s measure”.[5] It “wrests forms from
the
real world to which man is subject and make them enter a world in which
he is
the ruler”.[6]
All
this may seem rather abstract – and it inevitably is,
because I’m dealing with fundamental issues. Nevertheless, we see at
once that
the foundations of Malraux’s theory of art are very different from
those of
traditional aesthetics. There is no presumption, for example, that man
is
endowed with a certain “human nature” which includes an “aesthetic
sense” or a
“sense of taste” – both central Enlightenment beliefs. There is no
presumption
that man is a creature of historical circumstance and that History is
moving
towards a knowable goal. There is, in short, no absolute
that establishes man’s significance; there is only the
basic capacity, lying at the heart of human consciousness itself, to
call
creation into question, a capacity to which art gives a series of
answers, none
of them definitive. Art, Malraux writes, is “a series of provisional
responses to a question that remains intact”.[7] Now,
abstract though they are, these propositions give
Malraux the basis for a comprehensive theory of art covering a range of
major
issues, one of which is the nature of artistic creation, the issue to
which I
now turn. According
to one familiar view, which I’m sure you’ve all
encountered, the impulse to be an artist – the basic desire to paint,
to write,
or compose music – springs from a response to some aspect of what is
variously
called “the world around us”, or “reality”, or “life” – such as a
picturesque
scene in the case of a painter, an interesting person or incident for a
writer,
and perhaps a certain sequence of everyday sounds for the composer.[8]
Viewed in this light, the artist is first and foremost a person who
reacts to
“the world around him” or “reality” in an unusually sensitive way, and
then has
an urge to respond through some form of artistic expression. The basic
assumption is that the desire to be an artist, whether one succeeds or
fails,
springs essentially from a response to people, objects and incidents –
to “the
world”, “reality” or “life”. Now, as
one might expect, given the ideas outlined above,
Malraux rejects explanations of this kind. Where
art is concerned, the “reality” or “life” that matters – the
reality that
art seeks to resist – is, as we have seen, the chaotic world of
fleeting
appearances – the meaningless realm in which man counts for nothing.
And
understandably, it not this reality – the reality to which man is mere
subject and blind victim
– that first fires an ambition to be a painter, writer or composer; it
is an
encounter with those objects in which
that chaos has been overcome,
those objects in which man is no longer mere subject, but ruler – that is, existing art.
The painter, in other words, is first
inspired by paintings, the novelist
by novels, the poet by poetry, and the composer by music. Malraux finds
ample
evidence for his claim in the history of art. “It is a revealing fact”,
he
writes, that, when
explaining how his vocation came to him, every great artist traces it
back to
the emotion he experienced at his contact with some specific work of
art: a
writer to the reading of a poem or a novel, or a visit to a theatre; a
musician
to a concert he attended, a painter to a painting he once saw. Never do
we hear
of one who became an artist by suddenly, out of the blue, so to speak,
responding to an impulse to express some scene or startling incident.[9] Not
surprisingly then, Malraux rejects the familiar view
that the artist is essentially the man or woman who is “more sensitive
to life”
than others, and that the urge to become an artist results from this
sensitivity. “An artist is not necessarily more sensitive than an
art-lover,”
he writes, “and is often less so than a young girl”. The artist,
however, has a
sensitivity “of a different order”. He or she is sensitive above all to
art: “Just as a musician loves
music and
not nightingales, and a poet poems and not sunsets, a painter is not
primarily
a person who is thrilled by figures and landscapes. He is essentially
one who
loves pictures.” There is, in other words, no necessary correlation
between
“being sensitive” in the everyday sense, and being an artist; and just
as the
supremely gifted artist is not necessarily unusually sensitive in that
everyday
sense, so, Malraux argues, “the most sensitive man in the world is not
necessarily an artist”.[10] Malraux
then takes his thinking a step further. Given that
art, not “life”, is the artist’s point of departure, every great
artist, he
argues, “starts off with the pastiche”[11]
– that is by imitating the style of the artist or artists he
most admires, even if he is only vaguely aware of doing so. Again,
Malraux
argues, there is abundant evidence in the history of art: Goya’s
path led through Bayeu,[12] the
Impressionists’ path led through
traditional painting or Manet; Michelangelo’s through Donatello,
Rembrandt’s
through Lastmann and Elsheimer; El Greco’s through Bassano’s studio –
and
precocity simply means the ability to copy at an early age.[13] Genuine
artistic creation – as distinct from the pastiche
– occurs only when the artist senses that copying no longer suffices.
No longer
content with imitation, he begins to see, Malraux argues, that he is a
prisoner
of a style, and that speaking in someone else’s language “involves a
servitude
peculiar to the artist: a submission to certain forms and to a given
style”.[14]
Gradually glimpsing the possibility of a different unified world that
he or she
might bring into being, the artist starts to break free from the styles
that
had initially exerted such a powerful influence and begins, often
haltingly, to
develop another. Thus “it is against a style that every genius has to
struggle”,
Malraux writes; and “Cézanne’s architecturally ordered landscapes” (for
example) “did not stem from a conflict with trees and foliage, but from
a
conflict with painting as he knew it”.[15] The
ideas of “struggle” and “breaking free” are important
here and the vocabulary Malraux employs in this context regularly
suggests a
striving to overcome, a search for deliverance. Paradoxically, he
argues, the
artist’s discovery of his or her own style involves a form of
destruction.
“What differentiates the man of genius from the man of talent, the
craftsman or
the dilettante,” he writes, is not the
intensity of his responses to the world around him, nor only the
intensity of
his responses to the works of other artists; it is the fact that he
alone,
among all those who are fascinated by these works, also
seeks to destroy them.[16] This claim, initially puzzling though it
seems, flows necessarily from the basic propositions we have
considered. If,
for the artist, bare “reality” or “the world around us” is merely the
chaos of
fleeting appearances, the painter (or composer or poet) has only two
choices: to “copy
another painter – or to make
discoveries”: to follow an existing path or to blaze
new
trails.[17] Thus, in fulfilling a desire to create – to
emulate the
achievements of the artist or artists he most admires – the painter,
composer
or poet must therefore, paradoxically, eradicate
from his own work all
trace of the styles of those very artists. That is, in bringing a new,
unified
world into being, he must struggle against and eventually destroy,
in
his own work, the very styles that elicited so much admiration and gave
birth
to the desire to be an artist in the first place.[18] There is no middle way, so to speak, – no neutral
path, such as a “styleless” representation of the world, in which the
artist
might take temporary refuge. The options are simply the pastiche or
discovery –
to copy or to blaze new trails. The
proposition that there is no such thing as a
“styleless” representation of the world raises another issue we shall
consider
in a moment. This, however, is a good place to pause and consider a
possible
objection to the points made so far. Perhaps
one might say to Malraux that in placing such a
strong emphasis on the impact of existing art, he gives the impression
that the
artist somehow works in a vacuum, oblivious to the objects, shapes and
colours
in the world around him. Surely the world of objects and events must
play some part in the creative
process? This
objection would oversimplify Malraux’s argument. He fully accepts that
the
everyday world can serve as a resource, a “dictionary” of forms, that
may be an
important source of suggestions and intimations. The issue, however, is
one of
priorities. “The outside world,” he writes, can be
rich in suggestions – of colour, of line, and of the form the artist
“is after”
– for the artist who is looking for them, and on condition that he is
not
looking for them as for a pre-synthesised whole but in the sense that
great
wellsprings, their levels having built up, look for a watercourse to
follow as
a river. Under these conditions, the part played by living forms can be
immense; a vast “dictionary”, to borrow Delacroix’s term, will emerge
out of
limbo.[19]
And
illustrating the point by a concrete example, he adds: It was
perhaps when he noticed that a meditative look comes over a face when
the
eyelids are lowered that a Buddhist sculptor was moved to impart that
look of
meditation to a Greek statue by closing its eyes; but if he noticed the
expressive value of those closing eyes, it was because he was
instinctively
seeking amongst all the living forms a means of metamorphosing the
Greek face.[20] What the artist rejects, in other words, is
not “the world” per se but the relationships
within the world, or
more accurately the absence of relationships –
their fundamentally
arbitrary and chaotic nature. The world of objects, shapes and colours
can play
a major role – but as servant not master. And the sine qua non,
if
it is to play that role, is the artist’s pursuit of a new unified world
as he
strives to break free from the styles that had initially impressed him.
“There
are rich treasures in the cavern of the world,” Malraux writes, summing
up the
point, “but if the artist is to find them he must bring his torch with
him”. [21]
Here,
if I may, I’d like briefly to return to Malraux’s
claim, mentioned earlier, that the artist has only two options: to
“copy
another painter – or to make discoveries”: to follow an existing path,
or to
blaze new trails. This proposition, we recall, arose from his argument
that the
artist begins with the pastiche and that, in bringing a new unified
world into
being, must struggle against, and eventually destroy, the style or
styles that
had originally impressed him and given birth to the initial desire to
be an
artist. On Malraux’s account, as we saw, there is no middle way – no
intermediate position, such as a “styleless” representation of the
world, in
which the artist might take temporary refuge. Now, in response to this,
one
might perhaps argue that Malraux is giving an unduly restricted account
of the
artist’s options. Surely, one might say, there are other alternatives
apart
from, on the one hand, the style of some previous artist (or some
combination
of more than one existing style), and on the other, a new style that
the artist
himself has discovered? Surely, there is some “extra-stylistic” option
– a
“neutral” position, so to speak, that can, at least temporarily,
provide
another path? Malraux
calls this quite commonly held idea the “fallacy
of the neutral style”. In visual art, he writes, it is the notion that there
exists a styleless, photographic kind of drawing (though we know now
that even
a photograph has its share of style) which would serve as the
foundation of a
work, style being something added. The basis of this view, he continues, is
the idea that a living model can be copied “without any interpretation
or
expression”. But in fact, he argues, No such
copy has ever been made. Even in drawing this notion can be applied
only to a
small range of subjects: a standing horse seen in profile, but not a
galloping
horse … Can one imagine a drawing of a rearing horse, seen from in
front, in a
style that is not that of any school, or of any innovator? The notion
of
the neutral style, he adds, springs in
large measure from the idea of the silhouette: the basic neutral style
in
drawing would be the bare outline. But any such method if strictly
followed
would not lead to any form of art, but would stand in the same relation
to
drawing as an art as the bureaucratic style stands to literature.[22] The reasoning here flows directly from the
account of art we have been examining. If, for the artist, “the world
around
us” is at most a “dictionary” – an assemblage of elements combined in a
manner
that renders them incoherent – and if the artist replaces this with a
rival,
unified world, creation in art will always involve a process of
selection,
exclusion, and re-ordering – in short of transformation.
A “neutral
style” – that is, a procedure which, in the name of a supposed
“objectivity” or
“absolute realism” refused to transform – would
thus not be a
“styleless” art but no form of art at all. It would simply be an
abandonment of
the processes on which art necessarily depends. Here we
see how far Malraux’s understanding of art differs
from the popular view that art is essentially a form of representation.
This
familiar idea, which is often invoked in the case of visual art and
literature
(though less so for music) fosters the belief that the art is
essentially a kind
of “transcription” of the outside world onto the surface of a canvas or
into
the pages of a novel. From there, it is but a short step to suggest
that a
neutral style, which would transcribe reality with minimum stylistic
“interference”, or even none at all, would be a possibility. Malraux’s
analysis
implies that this line of thought rests on a fundamental
misunderstanding. To
the extent that it is even conceivable, a neutral style would be a form
of
depiction that had abandoned all but the last vestiges of the
procedures
available to art. In visual art, it would result at best in the bare
outline or
the silhouette. In literature, it would lead to the commercial or
bureaucratic
style where, similarly, language tends towards a limited range of
standard, “lifeless”
forms. To the extent it were possible, a neutral style would, in other
words,
lead merely to the sign – that is,
to
those limited uses of visual forms or language that merely suggest, or
“point
to”, living forms (as a silhouette of a standing horse might be used to
indicate the presence of horses) but it would stop well short of portraying any such form.[23]
The artist, Malraux is arguing, is not involved in transcribing
anything, but
in transforming.[24]
Certainly, representation, in the simple sense of including in a
picture forms
resembling real objects, is one of the tools or techniques available to
art –
like the varied uses of line or colour – but, on Malraux’s account, it
is no
more than that. As a form of endeavour – as a human activity – he is
contending,
art is never representation. Art is
the creation of a rival world, a
world that depends for its existence on a process of transformation of
“the
world around us”. “We are beginning to understand,” he observes, “that
representation is one of the devices of style, instead of thinking that
style
is a means of representation”.[25]
“Great artists,” he writes, summing up this view, “are not transcribers
of the
world; they are its rivals”.[26]
It
follows from all this that, for Malraux, the true work
of art is a creation in
the full sense of the
term: it is something that seems to emerge “out of nowhere”, a creation
ex nihilo. This is not to deny
that in practice the process of
artistic
creation is often preceded by a laborious apprenticeship, and Malraux
himself
writes that “frequently the artist has to expel
his masters
from his canvases bit by bit; sometimes their hold on him remains so
strong
that he seems, as it were, to insinuate himself into odd corners of his
picture”.[27]
That said, however, the true work of art is a creation ex
nihilo because its achievement depends on the complete
destruction of the style or styles from which it originated, with no
intermediate position – no neutral position – to occupy. It’s for this
reason
that Malraux has so little enthusiasm for accounts of the history of
art that
are, to use his words, “only
chronologies of
influences”.[28]
For
Malraux, art, as distinct from the pastiche, begins precisely where
influences cease. While
acknowledging that every
artist begins by imitating, and that influences in this
sense are the crucible out of which art emerges, he is
claiming, nonetheless, that only when those influences have been
eradicated
does art comes into being. A history of art that spoke of artistic
creation
solely in terms of influences – either on, or by, the art it describes
– would,
for Malraux, speak of everything except the essential. I said
at the beginning that I would say a few words about
why the topic of creation receives relatively little attention in
modern aesthetics
but I’ve left myself so little time I’ll need to keep my comments very
short. In essence,
creation fares badly,
in my view, because the two major sources of modern aesthetics –
Enlightenment
thought and nineteenth century thinkers such as Hegel and Marx – felt
their
prime concerns lay elsewhere. Enlightenment thinkers regarded art as a
given –
it was simply part of the human landscape they set out to explain – and
the
only question that mattered was how art could be linked up with the
models of
human nature they were developing. Hence the focus on ideas such as
aesthetic
sense, a judgement of taste, aesthetic pleasure and so on. For Hegel
and his
intellectual descendants, the situation has been similar, with the
important
difference that the idea of human nature they had in mind now included
the role
of history. Again, however, art was essentially a given – part of the
human
landscape – and the focus lay not on what creation might mean in the
case of
art, but on explaining the relationship between art and history. The
relative
lack of interest philosophers of art show in artistic creation today
is, I
think, a consequence of this historical inheritance. Modern aesthetics
is
heavily indebted to its 18th and 19th
century forbears –
more so than it often likes to admit – and this not only affects the
way it
thinks, but what it thinks about – and doesn’t
think about. Creation is art is a good example. It was
not high on the
agenda before, and it still isn’t now. For Malraux, by contrast, art is
not simply a given; he
explains its very
existence. Hence the important role creation plays in his thinking. [1] La Métamorphose des
dieux, 37. Antimémoires, 7 [2] André Malraux, La Tête
d’obsidienne, (Paris:
Gallimard, 1974),
221. All translations from
French sources are my own. [3] Ibid. [4] Ibid. [5] André Malraux, “Articles de ‘Verve’: De la
représentation en Occident et en Extrême Orient,” in Ecrits
sur l'Art (I), ed. Jean-Yves Tadié (Paris: Gallimard, 2004),
931-940, 933. [6] Les Voix
du silence, 539. [7]
Les Voix du silence, 887. [8] In the case of music, the logic is sometimes
abandoned and it is suggested that a composer is inspired by scenes or
events
rather than sounds. This perhaps reflects an uncomfortable feeling that
a
sequence of everyday sounds seems an unlikely origin for a symphony or
concerto, for example. As Malraux puts it (also commenting on the
conventional view),
“A composer seems less likely to have become one out of a love for
nightingales
than a painter to have become a painter out of love for landscapes.” Les Voix du silence, 502. [9] Ibid., 497. Malraux also neatly encapsulates
the point in a comment on the well-known legend about Giotto. “An old
story
goes,” he writes, “that Cimabue was struck with admiration when he saw
the
shepherd-boy, Giotto, sketching sheep. But, in the true biographies [of
artists], it is never the sheep that inspire a Giotto with the love of
painting, but rather the paintings of a man like Cimabue.” Les Voix du silence, 497. Cf. “No
shepherd became a Giotto by
looking at his sheep”. L'Homme précaire
et la littérature 125. [10] Les Voix
du silence, 494. [11] Ibid., 531. [12] Francisco Bayeu (1734-1795), one of Goya’s
early teachers and mentors. [13] Les Voix
du silence, 526. In a similar vein, Malraux writes in L’Homme précaire et la littérature:
“Rimbaud did not begin by
writing a kind of vague, formless Rimbaud, but with Banville; and the
same is
true, if we substitute other names instead of Banville, for Mallarmé,
Baudelaire, Nerval, Victor Hugo. A poet does not begin with something
vague and
formless but with forms he admires.” L'Homme
précaire et la littérature 155. [14] Les Voix
du silence, 582. [15] Ibid. [16] Ibid. Malraux’s emphasis. [17] Ibid., 537. [18] The idea can, however, be exaggerated. One
early critic argues that for Malraux “the artist … is essentially
demonic, and
his demonism is directed against the forms of his predecessors, which
he is
trying to devour…” John Darzins, “Malraux and the Destruction of
Aesthetics,” Yale French Studies 18
(1957): 108. This
distorts Malraux’s point. [19] Ibid., 570. As he acknowledges, Malraux is
borrowing the term “dictionary” in this sense from Delacroix. (See Les Voix du silence, 570.) The thinking
here is not limited to visual art. In L’Homme
précaire et la littérature, Malraux uses the same concept of
a “Delacroix’s
dictionary” in the context of an analysis of literary creation. L'Homme précaire et la littérature 157. [20] Les Voix
du silence, 573. [21] Ibid. [22] Ibid., 534. [23] As this analysis suggests, Malraux’s theory of
art provides no support for the claim advanced in certain “semiotic”
theories –
of which there are several variants – that art is essentially a system
of
signs. Malraux agrees that art occasionally makes
use of signs, but in itself the sign is, on his account, only
an embryonic
form of art. (See Ibid., 534, 543, 544.) [24] Cf. “Whatever he might say, [the artist] never submits to the world, and always
submits the world to that which he substitutes for it. His will to
transform is
inseparable from his nature as artist.” André Malraux, La
Psychologie de l'art: La Création Artistique (Paris: Skira,
1948), 156. Emphasis in original. [25] Ibid., 553.
[26] Ibid., 698. Emphasis in original. Malraux uses
this same statement as the epigraph to his final volume on art, L’Intemporel. Cf. also: “Like the
painter, the writer is not the transcriber of the world; he is its
rival.” L'Homme précaire et la littérature 152.
[27] Les Voix
du silence, 570. [28] Ibid., 879. Cf. “The history of art is the
history of forms invented in place of (“contre”) those inherited.”
Ibid., 582. |
|