Why
art is never representation (even
when it
represents) This
is a slightly edited version of a paper I
delivered a conference at the Australian National University in
December 2017.
The images are from the PowerPoint presentation that accompanied the
paper.
I don’t
want to lead you down the highways and byways of these debates. They’ve
been
going on, more or less fruitlessly, for decades now and are, in my
view, among
the more tedious and arid areas of analytic aesthetics which, at the
best of
times, tends, regrettably, to be a rather tedious and arid affair
anyway. Yet I
suppose we do have to admit one thing. There is a tendency for many of
us to
assume, more or less unthinkingly, that art – especially visual art and
literature – does somehow, in some ill-defined way, “represent the
world”. We
struggle to apply the proposition to art forms such as music of course
– with
the doubtful exception of so-called program music – but it’s
nonetheless hard
to rid ourselves entirely of the belief that paintings like the Mona Lisa, or Titian’s Man
with a Glove, for example,
“represent” certain people, or that novels like War
and Peace or Balzac’s Père
Goriot – “represent”
life in a certain
place at a certain period of history. And from there, it seems just a
short
step to assume that representation is what art is really about. Nevertheless,
it is this belief – that art is essentially representation – that I
want to question
today, building my case on an excellent analysis by André Malraux in one
of his major works on
the theory of art – Les Voix du silence –
a work, incidentally, that writers in aesthetics, both here in
Australia and
overseas, almost never read, and whose very existence they often seem
quite unaware
of. Malraux does not, of course, argue that art – visual art for
example –
never represents anything. Such a claim would obviously not be
sustainable. But
he does argue – and argue quite passionately – that the essential
purpose of art is not to represent the world, whether or
not, as in the case of the two paintings I have just mentioned, something is obviously represented.
Malraux’s
analysis here, as this implies, is not about individual works, but
about the fundamental nature and purpose of
art –
the general function it performs in human life – whether we’re speaking
of
visual art, literature or music. I
won’t
have time to explain his position in full, but I do want to comment on
certain aspects
of his argument that are relevant to our conference’s topic. Now, at
one level, it seems perfectly reasonable to say that these three images
are all
representations of horses, in each case in a different style – the
style of an
unknown Palaeolithic cave painter, the style of Rubens, and the style
of a
photograph. And if that seems a reasonable thing to say, one inference
we might
feel inclined to draw is that each image is a different stylistic
rendering of an
underlying, stylistically neutral
representation of a horse – that is, an underlying representation that
is free
not of only of these three styles,
but of any specific style – a
basic,
style-less image, so to speak. Seen in this light, the notion of style
would, as
André
Malraux points out, be understood as “successive varieties of ornament
added to
an immutable substratum”[1]
–
that is, a kind of “added layer” which, in theory at least, could be
jettisoned
altogether if the artist so desired. This tempting idea is what Malraux
calls
“the fallacy of a neutral style”. In visual art, he writes, “it has
been
assumed for centuries that there exists a styleless, ‘photographic’
kind of
drawing (though we know now that every photograph has its share of
style) which
would serve as the foundation of a work, style being something added.
This is
the fallacy of a neutral style.” Now, I
must in all honesty confess that before I started to think seriously
about
these issues, I myself probably subscribed to a view something like the
one
Malraux describes, and perhaps I am not only one who has done so? After
all,
the proposition seems plausible enough on the surface, does it not?
Don’t we
often tend to assume that the specific style in which an object is
portrayed is
something “added” as Malraux writes – so that Rubens, for example, adds
a
rather more flamboyant style to his horse than the Lascaux painter and
the
camera? And don’t we often tend to assume, even if in a vague sort of
way, that
if we were to somehow to remove this something “added”, we would be
left with a
basic, style-free image of the object – an “immutable substratum” to
borrow
Malraux’s phrase? I
suspect I had a
definite tendency to think that way – and if I am ruthlessly honest, I
suspect
I thought about literature in a similar way, assuming that each
novelist, for
example, adds his or her particular style to a kind of underlying
neutral style
which, as Malraux says, served as the foundation for the various final
products. As he so
often does, however, Malraux encourages us to examine our assumptions
more
carefully. The basis of the idea of the neutral style, he writes, is
the idea
that a living model can be copied “without any interpretation or
expression”.
But, in reality, he points out, No such copy has
ever been made. In drawing, this
notion can be applied only to a small range of subjects [such as] a
standing
horse seen in profile…Can one imagine a drawing of a rearing horse,
seen from
in front, in a style that is not that of any school, or of any
innovator? The notion of a
style-less drawing, he writes, springs in large
measure from the idea of the
silhouette: the basic neutral style in drawing would be the bare
outline. But
any such method, if strictly followed, would not lead to any form of
art, but
would stand in the same relation to drawing as an art as the
bureaucratic style
stands to literature. The
argument is intriguing, but is it correct?
Well, one can test it fairly easily. My
photoshopping abilities are
unfortunately rather limited but I’ve managed to reduce the photograph
of
certain object to its silhouette. (I would have included a bare outline
as well
but that proved to be beyond my capacities.) Here is that object. What
exactly
is it, I wonder? Well, with
a little imagination we can probably manage to make out what it is. I
took my
cue from Malraux’s statement and chose a photograph of a rearing horse,
seen
from in front – though I wasn’t able to find one taken from exactly in
front. The
silhouette makes perfect sense once we see the photograph, but without
it, we
struggle a little, do we not? – and we’d struggle even more, I suspect,
with a
silhouette or outline from directly in front. The silhouette or the bare
outline shows us an image “without any interpretation or expression”,
to borrow
Malraux’s words; and in this case, we don’t even have the
interpretation or
expression afforded by a photograph. But the result is not the readily
recognisable image of a horse executed in a “neutral style”: it is not
a
“style-less” image of a horse – an immutable substratum; it is merely
an image
that, in a case such as this, borders on the unintelligible – something
not
terribly far from a meaningless blob. Now,
already we can perhaps see that Malraux’s analysis poses a major threat
to the
proposition that art is essentially a form of representation.
Philosophers of
art define the idea of representation in various ways, not all of which
are
very helpful, but at their core, most definitions imply a close and
direct
relationship between the work of art and what one might loosely call
“the
outside world” or “reality”. If art is essentially representation, the
arguments imply, its function relies heavily on a presumed capacity to
reflect
that world – to hold a mirror up to nature in Hamlet’s words.
Seen in this
light, the essential task of the artist is to effect a kind of
transposition or
transcription of the outside world, or “reality”, onto the surface of a
canvas
or into the pages of a novel. And not surprisingly, this thinking often
goes
hand in hand with the familiar claim – quite understandable in this
context –
that a prime virtue of the true artist is “faithfulness to reality”.
And going
on from there, taking what seems to be the next logical step, one might
even
argue that a neutral style, that
would transcribe reality with maximum faithfulness to nature and
minimum
“interference” by the artist’s style, or even none at all, might be a
real
possibility. Malraux’s
analysis suggests that thinking of this kind rests on a basic
misunderstanding.
To the extent that it is even conceivable, a neutral style would not be
pure,
unalloyed realism but a form of depiction that had in fact abandoned
all but
the last vestiges of the procedures available to art. In visual art, it
would,
as we have seen, be at best the bare outline or the silhouette. In
literature,
it would, as Malraux suggests, lead merely to the commercial or
bureaucratic
style where, in a similar way, language tends towards a limited range
of
standard, “lifeless” forms. To the extent it is conceivable, in other
words, a
neutral style would result at best in the
sign – that is, to those limited uses of visual forms or
language that
merely suggest, or “point to”, living forms – as a silhouette of a
standing
horse might be used to indicate the presence of horses – but it would
stop well
short of portraying any such form,
as
Rubens and our Palaeolithic painter do. Which is why, incidentally,
Malraux
gives scant support to semiotic theories of art. He is happy to agree
that art
sometimes makes use of signs, but
in
itself, he argues, the sign is at best only an embryonic form of art.[2]
` But if art
is not essentially representation,
what is it? To explore Malraux’s answer, I’d like to approach our topic
from a
slightly different angle. In the same section of Les
Voix du silence I’ve been discussing, Malraux reminds us of
an
obvious point that we – or at least I – often tend to forget. He points
out
that painting (like the photograph) always involves a process of reduction – that is, a process by which
the painter reduces a world of three dimensions to one of two
dimensions. This
being so, the painter’s task inevitably requires a process of
selection,
exclusion, and re-ordering – in short, a process of transformation
– a process in which, even if the aim is to create
an illusion of a three-dimensional reality (as in Renaissance art for
example),
the painter is not transcribing or transposing the outside world, but transforming it, that is, quite
literally creating another world, a
world different in kind from the
world in which we live and move. One might
perhaps object that this argument does not hold good for sculpture
since, in
that case, the artist is not obliged to reduce three dimensions to two,
and
exact replicas of real objects are quite possible. But Malraux’s
rejoinder is
that sculpture too involves a process of reduction – a reduction of
“movement,
implicit or portrayed, to immobility”. And although, he writes, “we can
imagine
a still life carved and painted to look exactly like its model, we
cannot
conceive of its being a work of art. Imitation apples in an imitation
bowl are
not a true work of sculpture”. Which is why, he adds interestingly,
“colours applied
to sculpture so rarely imitate those of the real world; and why
everyone feels
that wax figures (the only forms in our time that are completely
illusionist)
have nothing to do with art”.[3]
Some
critics, including several art historians, have misread all this and
claimed
that Malraux’s argument is in fact intended as an attack
on representational art and that he has a bias against it– a
claim which, incidentally, reveals that the critics in question cannot
have
read Malraux with any care, given his enormous admiration for works
ranging
from medieval and Buddhist sculpture, to Titian and Rembrandt, to
modern
painters such as Van Gogh and Renoir, and many more. But in any case,
the
issue, as I have said, is not about individual works, or whether art
that
represents might somehow be better or worse than art that doesn’t –
questions
that Malraux would have doubtless regarded as absurd; our concern is
the quite
different matter of the fundamental nature and purpose of art. And in
that
context, Malraux’s argument is that representation, in the simple sense
of
including in a picture forms resembling real objects, is simply one of
the tools or techniques available
to art –
like the varied uses of line or colour. As a form of endeavour – as a
certain
kind of human achievement – he is contending, art is never essentially
representation. (“It is for the non-artist, not the artist,” he writes,
“that
painting is only a form of representation”.[4])
Art always involves the creation of another world – a rival
world, as he often says, a world that depends for its very
existence on a process of transformation of bare “reality” or “the
outside
world”. A theory
of this kind, it is worth noting, offers a much clearer and more
coherent
explanation of the notion of style than the theory that art is
essentially
representation. If the goal of art is simply to represent – to
transcribe the
outside world into a novel or onto a canvas as faithfully as possible –
what
after all, is the function of style? Style in that case begins, as we
have
seen, to look suspiciously like a potential source of interference
– perhaps of distortion – and it’s no accident, I
think, that writers in aesthetics who claim that art is essentially
representation typically skirt around the question of style, or fall
back on
variants of the idea that it is, to borrow Malraux’s words again,
something
“added” or “successive varieties of ornament”. The proposition that art
exists
to create another world, however, gives a clear and decisive meaning to
the
idea of style. Styles are the very fabric of art; they are the
different ways
in which the artist accomplishes the transformation that creates a
rival world.
In some cases, those means might include the representation of real
objects; in
others, they may not. But in all cases, style is never simply something
“added”; it is the essential, indispensable means through which the
artist creates another world, “no
less necessary”,
Malraux writes, “when the artist is aiming at unlikeness than when he
aims at
life-likeness”.[5]
The role of representation
itself then becomes quite clear. “We are beginning to understand,” he
writes,
“that representation
is one of the devices of
style, instead of thinking that style is a means of representation”.[6]
There is
much more to say about Malraux’s theory of art. If art is the creation
of a
rival world, what is the purpose of that world? What function does it
perform
in human life? These questions go to the heart of Malraux’s theory of
art and explain
many of its fascinating features – including his revolutionary claim,
whose
importance is still widely unrecognised, that art does not endure
timelessly as
the West has believed for so many centuries, but through an endless
process of
metamorphosis. But those are questions for another day because my time
has now
expired. [1]
Les Voix du silence, 540. [2]
See
Les Voix du silence, 534, 543,
544. [3]
Ibid. This would not of course preclude certain real objects – “objets
trouvés”
– being regarded as art, either as parts of a sculpture or as the
“sculpture”
itself. A piece of driftwood displayed as art is not viewed as a
representation
of a piece of driftwood (as a wax model is of a particular person). [4]
Les Voix du silence, 538. [5]
Les Voix du silence, 491. [6]
Ibid., 553. [7]
Ibid., 698. Emphasis in original. Malraux uses this same statement as
the
epigraph for his final volume on art, L’Intemporel.
Cf. also: “Like the painter, the writer is not the transcriber of the
world; he
is its rival.” L’Homme précaire et la
littérature, 152. |