Laclos and the Dark Side of the Enlightenment
This is a paper I presented to the British
Society for Eighteenth-Century Studies Annual Conference, January 2010, St
Hugh's College, Oxford. The Enlightenment, as we know, has
fallen on hard times in recent decades. Traditionally it has been regarded the luminous
Age of Reason – the age of the French philosophes,
of English thinkers such as Hume and Hutcheson, the age in which militant
Reason overthrew the last bastions of religious superstition and feudal
authoritarianism to usher in a new world of individual rights, tolerance, human
dignity, science, and progress. More recently, however, the Enlightenment has
been painted in rather different colours. The “Enlightenment project”, as the
modern phrase has it, is now often depicted as the underlying cause of many of
contemporary ills – a cultural and philosophical movement that promised
civilised values and human dignity but in fact delivered two World Wars, the
horrors of the Nazi Holocaust, and a world of continuing violence and oppression.
For thinkers of this persuasion, such as Adorno, Levinas, Lyotard, and
Foucault, the Age of Reason was, strange though it may seem, the origin of our modern
catastrophe. I don’t wish to get embroiled in this
debate, or to take sides in it. The Enlightenment continues to have its
defenders as well as its accusers, and I suspect that the issues dividing them will
remain in dispute for some time to come. My aim today is to call attention to an
error, or at least an oversight, which, it seems to me, is sometimes committed
by thinkers on both sides of this polemical
fence – an error that tends to misrepresent the Enlightenment by giving a
one-dimensional view of its intellectual achievement. Essentially, I would argue, thinkers
on both sides of this debate think of the Enlightenment in roughly the terms I have
mentioned: that it was an optimistic new era in Western civilization that
raised high the banners of reason, science, individual rights, tolerance, human
dignity, and progress. Opinions are now divided about the intellectual and historical
consequences of the event – that is, whether
these lofty ideals masked tendencies of a more sinister and destructive kind;
but there tends, nonetheless, to be widespread agreement in both camps that the
Enlightenment itself saw its
achievements – and especially the triumph of Reason – in wholly positive terms,
and looked to the future with more or less unqualified faith in the new values
it was establishing. Now, undeniably, it is very difficult
to read the philosophical writings of the eighteenth century without sensing the
widespread enthusiasm for the new horizons that were opening up. And although
the French Revolution’s “Festival of Reason” was a short-lived affair, the fact
that it was held at all testifies to the immense prestige associated with this
central Enlightenment value by the late eighteenth century. But if we look a
little more closely, we begin to see, I believe, that there were certain figures
at the time – admittedly a small minority – who, despite a strong attachment to
Enlightenment values, were, nonetheless, rather less sanguine about some of the
implications of this new Age of Reason – figures who are much less easy to fit
into the conventional image of the Enlightenment I have alluded to. The names that spring most readily to
mind in this connection, I think, are Goya in his late period, de Sade, and the
writer I want to say something about today, Choderlos de Laclos, author of Les Liaisons Dangereuses. None of these three,
I should say, was in any sense an opponent of Enlightenment values, hankering for
a return of the previous dispensation. Goya fell foul of the Spanish
authorities for his libertarian sympathies; Sade was, as we know, fiercely
anti-religious, and Laclos was a strong supporter of the French Revolution. All
three were partisans of Reason, so to speak, but each, nonetheless, discovered that
the universe of Reason has some unexpected, and at times forbidding,
inhabitants. They expose, if you will excuse the unintended echo of Star Wars, what I call the “dark side”
of the Enlightenment – the side that the conventional picture often ignores but
which, surely, we cannot afford to ignore
if we wish to give an accurate account of the event and, just as importantly, of
its implications for us today. Why do I say disturbing? In essence, I
think, because the reader wants to condemn the actions of Merteuil and Valmont unreservedly;
yet there is something about both of them – something not easy to pin down – that
seems to command our respect, however unwillingly we give it. I want now to
spend a few moments looking at their characters a little more closely to see
what that something might be. The difference, essentially, I would
argue, is that for the Marquise de Merteuil and the Vicomte de Valmont
deception and the manipulation of others is a way of life – almost an end in
itself. Iago manipulates Othello because he is envious and wants revenge; Gil
Blas is tricked by a flatterer who wants to inveigle money out of him; Tom
Jones is deceived to ruin his chances with his beloved Sophia. But while
Merteuil and Valmont also have their objectives – the desires they wish to
satisfy – in their case these seem to be secondary – almost, I would say,
pretexts. Merteuil’s plan to ruin Cécile Volanges is certainly motivated by her
desire to settle scores with one of her former lovers, Gercourt, but as André
Malraux comments – correctly I think – this is little more than mere
information for the reader – a kind of necessary trigger for the plot. There is
no question of a genuine hatred for Gercourt – of a passion thirst for revenge.
Merteuil deceives, in other words, essentially because she wishes to live in a
world in which she controls the actions
of others, and the same can be said for Valmont. Certainly, Valmont admires
Mme de Tourvel, and eventually even develops a kind of love for her – even if,
as Merteuil points out, it is nothing more than the love a Sultan might feel
for his chief Sultana; but fundamentally Valmont deceives for the same reason
Merteuil deceives – so that he will always act in accord with what he calls his
“principles”, and those principles, like Merteuil’s, do not merely require the
satisfaction of a desire. They require the conduct of an accomplished general
on a field of battle who controls his enemy’s movements by skilful deception,
and who wins the battle not by mere force but by feints and manoeuvres, and who
glories not simply in the victory but in the skill and intelligence that
brought it about. What is this so? The answer, I would
argue, is that Merteuil and Valmont, are true children of the Enlightenment –
truer than we might suspect – and they do not simply believe in the value of
Reason in an abstract, philosophical sense; they have resolved to live the life of Reason – to think and
act, in their relationships with others, in ways that never offend against the requirements
of lucid, rational thought. What does this mean exactly? What does it mean to “live
the life of Reason”? I think it’s useful here to compare Les Liaisons Dangereuses with a work of
a very different kind, let’s say Shakespeare’s Romeo and Juliet. For both Romeo and Juliet, as for the play’s
audience, their love for each other is ultimately an unexplained fact – a given – that they and the audience
simply accept as part of their unfolding story. Love in this sense is truly a
passion in the sense that it simply takes hold, overwhelms, and compels one to follow
its path – come what may – without fully understanding it. I do not mean, of
course, that Romeo and Juliet have nothing to say about their love; on the
contrary it’s a topic they discourse on endlessly. But their love for each
other, like that of Tristan and Isolde, or of the Princesse de Clèves and the Duc
de Nemours, or even of Tom Jones and his Sophia, remains nevertheless, in
essence, a coup de foudre in the
French phrase – a fate, a destiny, so to speak, that simply descends on them
and which, while occupying their thoughts to the point of obsession, rules over
them far more than they rule it. For Merteuil and Valmont, however,
the case is very different. For both characters, any action worth pursuing must
be accompanied by, and justified by, its explanation – its reason. This is why
Malraux comments, very aptly I think, that Les
Liaisons Dangereuses is a novel that talks a lot about passion, but in
which passion is in fact almost completely absent – the one exception being
Madame de Tourvel who finally yields unreservedly to Valmont. Romeo and Juliet
– to pursue my comparison a little further – are pledged to each other “come
what may” – for good or ill: their love is their “fate”. For Merteuil and
Valmont, by contrast, the world of “fate” is anathema – or, rather, it is the
world of fools. Their guiding principle is, precisely, that nothing should be left to fate, that
everything should be calculated in advance. Not, of course, that they are clairvoyants
with foreknowledge of future events. In fact, they are sometimes surprised by
unexpected developments – as Valmont is, for example, when Madame de Volanges
warns Madame de Tourvel about his disreputable past. What is at issue here,
however, is not a power of predicting the future but a particular manner of
thinking and acting. For Merteuil and Valmont, the only action worthy of the
name is one that is “thought-out” beforehand – an action constructed like a
move in a well-played game of chess where nothing is left to the vagaries of
fate. In such a world every act is accompanied by its explanation – its reason.
As Malraux succinctly puts it, Merteuil and Valmont are characters who “act
according to what they think”; and they do this consistently, right through to
the moment of victory. Near the end of the novel, as Valmont contemplates the
spectacle of Madame de Tourvel finally confessing her love for him, he reflects
for a moment on the possibility of not taking advantage of his conquest – of showing
some mercy for his victim. But the thought is instantly dismissed. To do so, he
tells himself, would be to betray his “principles” and act like a “foolish
school boy”. In the world of reason, there is simply no place for compassion –
for a senseless act that would simply undo a victory won and allow one’s prey to
escape. Compassion would be weakness – feebleness of mind. In the world of Reason
there is only victory or defeat; there are no other options. What is so curious about all this,
when we reflect on it, is that Merteuil and Valmont, who are undoubtedly among
the most abominable characters in eighteenth century fiction, are as I have
suggested, embodiments of a central Enlightenment value. The Enlightenment claimed
to scatter the forces of superstition and mystery, to subject everything to the
bright light of Reason, and reveal the general laws that govern the world. Its battle
cry is Kant’s injunction: “Sapere aude!” And Merteuil and Valmont, as we can
now see, do exactly that. Not that they claim to discover the “general laws of
human psychology”: they are not philosophers or armchair psychologists and
their aim is not to compile a list of abstract propositions about human nature.
Their mission is to introduce Reason into the world of human experience – to live and act in a world of Reason, to
live and act in a world in which lucidity triumphs over mystery and chance, a
world which, therefore, as a matter of felt experience, and not simply as
abstract concept, is a world governed by laws. The unexpected consequence,
however, as Laclos’ novel reveals, is that once established as the well-spring
of human action, this quintessentially Enlightenment value leads to forms of
human behaviour which seem wholly at variance with what, in an informal,
everyday sense, we might describe as an “enlightened” sensibility. Instead of valuing
equality, we discover a will to dominate; instead of a pursuit of truth we find
a will to mislead; and instead of compassion we discover an implacable will to humiliate
and destroy. In the realm of human sensibility – as distinct from the world of philosophical
abstractions – the bright light of Reason, in other words, quickly assumes a
dark and forbidding aspect, nurturing forces and dispositions which are the very
reverse of what one might hope for or expect. |